- Seppi-Cola
- Posts
- On Boethius
On Boethius
Literally the last shall be first
Medieval Thinker Project: Boethius
Joseph D. Sanns
Phil 201: History of Philosophy
Dr. Michael Arts
11 April 2025
Preface
This project isn’t written from the perspective of an expert or someone deeply steeped in medieval philosophy. I’m approaching Boethius as a first-time reader trying to make sense of his ideas through summaries, commentaries, and reflections from others all within a few short days of work and study. I’ve done my best to understand the heart of Boethius’s thought, but I recognize there are likely gaps or oversights in what I’ve picked up. This is a beginner’s map, not a comprehensive guide. Still, what follows is an honest attempt to engage with his work seriously and thoughtfully, to the extent that I can.
Biographical Information
Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius (c. 480–524 AD) was a Roman philosopher, statesman, and Christian theologian. Born into one of the last great senatorial families of Rome, Boethius inherited both political prestige and a deep classical education. He was raised in a world where Roman institutions still held symbolic power, but where actual control had passed into the hands of foreign rulers—most notably the Ostrogoths.
Boethius eventually rose to become magister officiorum, a kind of chief of staff or head of civil administration, under the Ostrogothic king Theodoric the Great. Theodoric ruled Italy after the fall of the Western Roman Empire, and although he was known behind closed doors by Roman elites as one of the “barbarian” kings, he sought to present himself more like a new Caesar—maintaining Roman laws, titles, and government structures. (Think: an Arian Christian warlord who also wanted to look like a Roman emperor.)
This uneasy coexistence between Roman tradition and Gothic rule worked—for a while. But beneath the surface, tensions lingered. The Senate remained loyal to Roman identity and orthodoxy, while Theodoric and his Gothic elite belonged to a different cultural and religious world. As diplomatic tensions rose between Theodoric and the Byzantine Empire (what was the eastern part of the Roman empire), the king’s trust in his Roman administrators began to falter. Boethius, despite his long service and loyalty to Roman ideals, was accused of treason for allegedly conspiring with the Byzantines. He was imprisoned and eventually executed.
It was during his imprisonment, while awaiting death, that Boethius composed his most famous work: The Consolation of Philosophy. Written as a dialogue between Boethius and a personified Lady Philosophy, the book offers a reflection on suffering, justice, fate, and the nature of happiness. Strikingly, the text makes no direct reference to Christian revelation—no Christ, no scriptures, no church. Though Boethius was a devout Christian, The Consolation was written as a work of reason, not of theology—perhaps in an effort to reach a universal audience, or perhaps as a deliberate return to classical methods in a moment of personal crisis.
That said, Boethius’s other works do engage directly with Christian doctrine. His theological treatises—including defenses of the Trinity and the dual nature of Christ—reflect a deep commitment to the intellectual defense of Christian orthodoxy. In this sense, Boethius stands at a pivotal moment in history: he is both the last great Roman philosopher and one of the first major voices of medieval Christian thought.
Boethius also played a crucial role in preserving ancient philosophy for the Latin-speaking West. His translations and commentaries on Aristotle, Porphyry, and other Greek thinkers introduced the tools of logic and metaphysics to early medieval scholars and helped lay the groundwork for the rise of scholasticism centuries later. The Consolation of Philosophy became one of the most widely read and imitated texts of the Middle Ages, shaping thinkers from Aquinas to Dante and beyond.
Below is a comprehensive list of his known works.
Critical Editions of the Complete Works of Boethius
Boethius, Theological Tractates and The Consolation of Philosophy, trans. H.F. Stewart, E.K. Rand, and S.J. Tester — Contains Boethius’s major philosophical and theological writings in a dual-language format. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1973)
Boethius, Opera Omnia, ed. Rudolfus Peiper and Gustavus Friedlein — A comprehensive Latin edition of Boethius’s collected works. (Leipzig: Teubner, 1871)
Boethius, De Institutione Musica, trans. Calvin M. Bower — A scholarly English translation of Boethius’s Neoplatonic treatise on music. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989)
Major Theological Publications
De Trinitate — A theological treatise using Aristotelian logic to explain the Christian doctrine of the Trinity. [Theological Tractates, Harvard University Press]
Utrum Pater et Filius et Spiritus Sanctus de divinitate substantialiter praedicentur — Explores how Trinitarian terms like “Father,” “Son,” and “Holy Spirit” can be applied to the divine essence without implying division. [ITheological Tractates, Harvard University Press]
Quomodo substantiae bonae sint cum non sint substantialia bona — Investigates how created substances can be called “good” without being goodness itself. [Theological Tractates, Harvard University Press]
Contra Eutychen et Nestorium — A defense of orthodox Christology against the errors of Eutychianism and Nestorianism. [Included in Theological Tractates, Harvard University Press]
Major Philosophical Publications
The Consolation of Philosophy (De Consolatione Philosophiae) — Boethius’s most famous work, written in prison, presenting a dialogue with Lady Philosophy on fortune, justice, happiness, and divine providence. [Oxford World’s Classics (P.G. Walsh), Penguin Classics (V.E. Watts), and Loeb Classical Library]
Major Logical Publications
Categoriae, De Interpretatione, Isagoge — Boethius’s translations and commentaries on Aristotle’s and Porphyry’s foundational logical texts. These works introduced formal logic to the Latin West. [Available from Catholic University of America Press]
De Divisione, De Definitione, De Syllogismo Categorico, De Syllogismo Hypothetico, Introductio ad Syllogismos Categoricos, De Differentiis Topicis — Boethius’s original treatises on logic, covering classification, definition, and syllogistic reasoning. [Catholic University of America Press]
Mathematical and Musical Publications
De Institutione Arithmetica — An introduction to number theory based on Nicomachus of Gerasa, presenting arithmetic as a philosophical discipline. [Catholic University of America Press]
De Institutione Musica — A Neoplatonic account of music’s role in personal ethics and cosmic order, integrating mathematical and metaphysical insight. [Translated by Calvin M. Bower, Yale University Press]
De Geometria — A short and possibly unauthentic work on geometry, preserved in manuscript collections. [Included in Opera Omnia, Teubner edition]
Lost or Uncertain Works
De Astronomia – Referred to in his own writings, but no manuscript survives.
Mathematical and Musical Works
Boethius attempted to preserve the quadrivium traditions: arithmetic, music, geometry, and astronomy.
Works on rhetoric and grammar
Part of his larger plan to preserve all seven liberal arts; largely lost or unconfirmed.
Works Translated into English
These are widely available in English translation, often with commentary:
Philosophy & Theology
The Consolation of Philosophy – Multiple English translations, including Loeb Classical Library, Penguin Classics, and others.
De Trinitate (On the Trinity) – Translated in the Theological Tractates (Loeb).
Utrum Pater et Filius et Spiritus Sanctus de divinitate substantialiter praedicentur – Included in Loeb's Theological Tractates.
Quomodo substantiae bonae sint cum non sint substantialia bona – In Theological Tractates volumes.
Contra Eutychen et Nestorium – Included in Loeb and other collected editions.
Logic and Dialectic
Isagoge (Porphyry’s Introduction, with Boethius’s commentaries) – Available in English via translations of the Commentaries on Porphyry.
Categoriae (Aristotle’s Categories) – Boethius’s translation and commentary are included in collections of early medieval logic.
De Interpretatione – Translation and commentary available in English.
De Divisione – Translated in collections on medieval logic.
De Definitione – Translated.
De Syllogismo Categorico – Available in English in logic anthologies.
De Syllogismo Hypothetico – Translated.
De Differentiis Topicis – Available in English (e.g., by Stump or Spade).
Mathematics & Music
De Institutione Arithmetica – English translation exists, usually published alongside Nicomachus.
De Institutione Musica – Translated, widely studied in the history of music theory.
Works Not Fully Translated or Uncertain
These are fragmentary, disputed in authorship, or not extant at all:
De Geometria – A Latin work attributed to Boethius, but its authenticity is debated. An English translation exists in parts, but it's less widely available due to the uncertain attribution and limited content.
De Astronomia – Lost. Mentioned by Boethius himself, but no manuscript survives Therefore, not translated.
Treatises on rhetoric and grammar – Believed to have been written or planned, but they have not survived and are not available in any language.
Short Summaries of Major Ideas
Free Will and Divine Foreknowledge
Boethius addresses the question of whether God's complete knowledge of the future means that human choices aren't really free. His answer is that God's knowledge is different from ours—God doesn’t exist in time like we do. He sees all of history at once, not moment by moment. So while it might look like God “knows the future,” from His perspective there isn’t a future or past at all—just an eternal present. That means He can know what we choose without forcing us to choose it. Boethius uses this idea to argue that divine foreknowledge doesn’t cancel out human freedom. It's a way to preserve both God's omniscience and our moral responsibility.
The Nature of True Happiness
In his dialogue with Lady Philosophy, Boethius is taught that true happiness is not found in fortune, power, or pleasure, but in the possession of the highest good, which is God. Earthly goods are transitory and cannot provide lasting fulfillment. He comes to see that real happiness is not about having control over external events, but about becoming a certain kind of person—someone whose inner life is grounded in virtue, reason, and a vision of the good that does not change.
Fortune and Suffering
Boethius uses the metaphor of the Wheel of Fortune to show how unpredictable life can be. One moment you’re up, the next you’re down. Relying on fortune makes you vulnerable, but facing hardship can help shape your character and point you toward what really matters. The wise person learns not to depend on the wheel’s gifts. Adversity, rather than a curse, becomes an opportunity for philosophical insight and spiritual purification.
Providence vs. Fate Providence
Boethius says, is God’s eternal plan, and Fate is how that plan plays out over time. Things may look chaotic to us, but from the higher view of Providence, everything fits together. This helps explain how there can be order and justice even when we don’t immediately see it. Fate is the unfolding of that plan in time. What may seem arbitrary under Fate is ordered from the perspective of Providence. This distinction allows Boethius to affirm divine justice even in the face of apparent chaos.
Secondary Sources
Chadwick, Henry. Boethius: The Consolations of Music, Logic, Theology, and Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
Marenbon, John. Boethius. Oxford University Press.
Magee, John. Boethius on Signification and Mind. Brill Academic.
Stewart, Hilda. The Idea of Order in the Consolation of Philosophy. Twayne Publishers.
King, Peter. “Boethius.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (online).
My Personal Reflection and Analysis: Boethius on Suffering and Freedom
As mentioned at the start of this project, I have not read all of Boethius’s original works in full—particularly The Consolation of Philosophy—my understanding of his ideas comes from secondary sources. Much of my sense of Boethius also comes indirectly, through the works of C.S. Lewis, whose fiction and theology reportedly contain Boethian themes in both form and content. So what follows is not a scholar’s deep reading, but rather a student’s effort to wrestle with Boethius’s legacy to the extent that I can, drawing on what I’ve read and what I’ve come to see through that lens—albeit imperfectly.
Boethius wrote The Consolation of Philosophy while in prison, knowing he might be executed. Instead of focusing on revenge or despair, Boethius turns to big questions: Why do bad things happen to good people? Can we still believe the world is fair when it clearly isn’t? What does it mean to be happy when everything goes wrong?
He doesn’t answer with scripture or religious arguments. Instead, he creates a conversation with “Lady Philosophy,” a kind of personified wisdom, who challenges him to think more clearly. She tells him that things like money, power, reputation, and even good luck aren’t solid foundations for happiness because they can all be taken away. Real happiness has to be rooted in something that can’t be lost—virtue, reason, and alignment with what is eternally good.
That idea lines up well with what many people of faith believe, including in the Latter-day Saint tradition. We’re taught that life is a time of testing and growth, and that things like suffering and loss can actually help us become more wise and more whole. Boethius’ version of this is philosophical rather than spiritual, but it still points in the same direction: we are meant to become the kind of people who can face instability without being undone by it. We are to be resilient and strong.
One of the most interesting parts of his philosophy tries to solve the tension between God’s foreknowledge and human freedom. If God knows everything, do we still have real agency? Boethius says yes—because God doesn’t see time like we do. He sees everything at once. That means He knows what we’ll choose without forcing us to choose it. It’s a thoughtful answer, and one that respects both divine knowledge and human responsibility.
What I take from Boethius is not that he figured everything out, not even close, but that he asked the right kinds of questions. He didn’t pretend suffering isn’t real. He just tried to understand how it might fit into a bigger picture. His writing reminds us that it’s okay to wrestle with hard things, and that clarity doesn’t always come from emotion or instinct—it sometimes comes from slowing down and thinking things through.
Boethius’s influence extends far beyond his own time. His blending of classical philosophy with a Christian worldview laid a foundation for centuries of medieval thought. Scholars such as Thomas Aquinas cited Boethius regularly, not only for his philosophical insights but also for his logical precision. His approach to the relationship between faith and reason prefigured key scholastic debates and helped shape the methods used in medieval universities.
In the modern era, Boethius's Consolation has found admirers as well. C.S. Lewis, for example, drew heavily on Boethian themes in both his fiction and nonfiction. In The Screwtape Letters, The Problem of Pain, and even in The Chronicles of Narnia, Lewis echoes Boethius’s ideas about the instability of worldly fortune, the redemptive role of suffering, and the grounding of happiness in something unchangeable. Lewis also found in Boethius a model for how to explore profound questions in a narrative form that is accessible and emotionally resonant. Like Boethius, Lewis uses imagined dialogue and storytelling to bring philosophical and theological issues to life.
More broadly, the structure of The Consolation—a prisoner seeking meaning in adversity through a philosophical dialogue—continues to resonate with readers navigating their own trials. The image of Lady Philosophy, calm and reasoned in the face of suffering, becomes a powerful metaphor for the way reason and moral clarity can provide peace even when circumstances do not. For writers like Lewis, and for many others, (hopefully for me as I take time to really dive-in to his writing) Boethius serves as sort of a companion in the search for enduring wisdom.